Meaning Dynamics

Meaning Dynamics

Part 1: Developing meaning dynamics

Meaning in life is a complex dynamical process. Not only does mankind “search for meaning”—it also finds meaning in every moment. This meaning does not reveal itself as a series of properties of static objects in some objective universe, but through the direct experience with which we necessarily construct our understanding of our world and the things within it. In other words, we do not perceive reality[1] but instead generate it—and with this, the objects that we see as being real and concrete display more than just physical properties. They present themselves as meaningful and thanks to this, the accounts of our lives are replete with meaning.

Meaningful moments feed into meaningful narrative and that narrative motivates actions that expose us to new meaningful moments. This process–unlike more direct processes like emotions (which are often reduced to single cause-effect instances, to apparent success)–stretches out across time. To study meaning is to study an extended, dynamical process that unfolds over moments, minutes, hours, days, months, and years. For this reason–despite its ubiquitous presence in everyday conversation–meaning has largely been treated as an intractable subject for formalization. However, a shift from substance to process-based reasoning[2] has given us new tools with which we can examine formerly intractable tangles of complexity–in this instance, meaning.

We’ll first be discussing useful approaches to other phenomenologically complex concepts: the Theory of Constructed Emotion reimagines emotions as a constructive process and REBUS and the Anarchic Brain shows how phenomena and information can come together. We’ll then launch into an exploration of meaning dynamics, where we carve meaning into immediate and narrative senses and talk about how these interact with each other in a way that can be modeled and predicted.

The second part is an explanation of a pilot study we will be running. Here, we will cover current methods of studying meaning and identify peak experiences as being hotbeds of immediate and narrative meaning and construct an experiment from some reliable triggers of these experiences (psychedelics, flow, etc.). We will propose that the stimuli that accompany psychedelic experiences can themselves lead to entrainment and flow and, ultimately, peak experiences. Then, we will describe the pilot experiment and the resulting predictions, as well as the significance of each possible result. Last, we will discuss future directions to take this experimental design.

Emotions

Process-based line of thinking is increasingly represented in maturing theories. Feldman Barrett’s Theory of Constructed Emotion proposes the following:

In every waking moment, your brain uses past experience, organized as concepts, to guide your actions and give your sensations meaning. When the concepts involved are emotion concepts, your brain constructs instances of emotion. (Barrett, 2016)

Emotions are constructed as needed in the moment in order to help us maintain allostasis—relative stability in a complex environment. The traditional view is (roughly) this:

There exists some set of basic emotions: fear, anger, sadness, happiness. These basic emotions developed in order to provide our ancestors extra survival points. Fear feels the way it does because this feeling produces running away from the things we should fear. Sadness helps us socially bond and learn to avoid stimuli that could make us sad. Happiness steers us towards good actions like having kids. More complex emotions are combinations of essential emotions. Angst is two parts sadness and one part anger. These emotions are revealed through facial expressions and modular neuronal firings—fear is in the amygdala and anger the amygdala and hypothalamus. We also reveal our emotions through some set of behaviors. Sadness means tears and frowns, anger means red faces and balled fists. This is of course a caricatured version of the classic view, but it isn’t that far off. At its core, the classic view of emotions is that they are essential, common kinds and that they feel the way that they do because this feeling drives us to action.

The Theory of Constructed Emotion maintains the action-based conclusion—emotions must cause us to act in some way or they wouldn’t have emerged in the first place. However, we could easily imagine building a robot that behaved similarly to a human in the face of danger: If a dangerous object is present, then the emotion-free robot must activate its jet propulsion escape mechanism. Most would not be tempted to say the functional behavior that sometimes follows the onset of an emotion is itself the same as the emotion—though the traditional account has treated these things as being the same in practice. People who are experiencing fear sweat like scared people do, have increased cortisol levels, raise their eyebrows, and either run or fight or freeze up. This view turns out to be practical for designing experiments but also turns out to produce rather wild variation that is folded into the “noise” category. It also doesn’t get at the thing that matters most here, which is that emotions feel like something at all. The way these feelings manifest themselves over hours, weeks, days, and years are not practically measurable. Yet, for however impractical the feelings are, it is these feelings that shape the world as we experience it—not the facts that underlie these feelings.

The Theory of Constructed Emotion rightly recognizes the primacy of affect at play here. Instead of treating emotions as serving some high-level function (e.g., see snake, run from snake), it treats emotions as constructions. These are constructed from affect (i.e., how we feel), context, and prior learning—all to serve a single purpose—maintain allostasis (Barrett et al., 2016). This construction process is not describable in physics-friendly terms, except at the margins. Yet emotions are entirely central to our experiences as humans and therefore deserve our continued understanding and inquiry. Similarly, describing emotions in purely evolutionary terms does them a disservice. We’ve developed language and culture and have altered our environments such that new and complex emotions are now possible to express and share. And, more ambitiously, we could say that it’s possible to experience new emotions that our ancestors never could have experienced. Still, the fundamental pieces for emotions have been in place for quite some time—what are these?

Minimally, affect, environment, and an agent. Again, these aren’t physics-friendly pieces, but this doesn’t mean they can’t be examined and modeled.

Affect

Though overly simplistic and incomplete, Russell and Barrett’s Core Affect provides a useful illustration of the dynamics underlying affect[3] (Russell & Barrett, 1999). According to Barrett, this affect is continuously accessed through interoception.

image1-1

Figure 1 - Russell and Barrett's Core Affect processes

Environment

The environment is accessed through sensory modalities—and our continued survival seems to indicate that we are passingly decent at generating models of the environment and moving ourselves around it.

Other critical aspects of the environment are the language and culture that let us navigate its complex and changing parts. Language lets us communicate our own emotions and learn new and novel emotions, as well as help us continually calibrate these through learning.

Lastly, the environment is full of other minds, real or imagined.

Agent

In Barrett’s view, humans might be the only animals with full-bodied emotions, though it’s entirely possible other beings have just as much or more affect. This is because emotions—as she has outlined them—require language and cultural learnings.

An agent acts in accordance with its own goals (though this is often not in any obvious manner, modeling agents necessarily assumes that goal-achieving underlies the decisions agents make).

Allostasis

Underneath affect, environment, and agency, emotions have one last critical dimension—their ability to maintain allostasis—the energy and metabolism regulation at the core of emotions, their raison d'être. The reason we can interocept in the first place is because it gives us an interface into what’s going on inside our bodies, which lets us plan out and act in accordance with whatever will maintain allostasis. This view also rests on predictive processing, which posits that the brain is always generating and updating mental models of our environments.


Together, emotions are constructions of an agent in an environment, generated to maintain allostasis as a bottom line. While we don’t have to tie ourselves to all of Barrett’s claims or the claims underneath her claims, the allostatic approach is promising and may be useful for describing more than constructed emotions. Namely, we can borrow this triadic relationship and its dynamics: agent, environment, and goal.

REBUS and the Anarchic Brain

Carhart-Harris and Friston took a similar approach to bridging high and low-level phenomena in a very different space—psychedelics. Instead of focusing on metabolism and energy at the level of an organism, they modeled the apparent shifts in mental states between normal waking states and those experienced while under the influence of a psychedelic (e.g., psilocybin, LSD). They call this REBUS (Relaxed Beliefs Under Psychedelics, a tortured acronym):

…via their entropic effect on spontaneous cortical activity—psychedelics work to relax the precision of high-level priors or beliefs, thereby liberating bottom-up information flow, particularly via intrinsic sources such as the limbic system (R. L. Carhart-Harris & Friston, 2019).

Where Barrett’s view was about making predictions within an expansive and dynamic environment (i.e., the world that we live in), Carhart-Harris and Friston focus on even higher-level predictions (described as priors here), such as beliefs. Psychedelics relax the restraints on bottom-up information flow, allowing us to more directly interface with our sensory signals. Not only does this result in a subjectively interesting experience—where colors are brighter and sounds are more vibrant—but it also results in more enduring changes to “precision weighting of pathologically overweighted priors underpinning various expressions of mental illness”. In other words, the relaxation of priors directly and enduringly alters pathways that lead to mental health issues such as anxiety and depression, as an effect of their rigidity. This work ultimately rests on the demonstrated efficacy (Davis et al., 2020; Grob et al., 2011; Vermetten et al., 2020) of psychedelics in treating a variety of pathologies marked by their stubbornness.

From the physics and modeling-friendly perspective, the REBUS model also points to a particular kind of serotonin (5-HT2AR) as a driver of change:

The basic idea—pursued in this article—is that psychedelics act preferentially via stimulating 5-HT2ARs on deep pyramidal cells within the visual cortex as well as at higher levels of the cortical hierarchy. Deep-layer pyramidal neurons are thought to encode posterior expectations, priors, or beliefs. The resulting disinhibition or sensitization of these units lightens to precision of higher-level expectations so that (by implication of the model) they are more sensitive to ascending prediction errors (surprise/ascending information)… Computationally, this process corresponds to reducing the precision of higher-level prior beliefs and an implicit reduction in the curvature of the free-energy landscape that contains neuronal dynamics. Effectively, this can be thought of as a flattening of local minima, enabling neuronal dynamics to escape their basins of attraction and—when in flat minima—express long-range correlations and desynchronized activity.

At the neurophysiological level, 5-HT2ARs get agonized by the psychedelic, leading to hypersensitivity to context—this in turn presses the overall network to change itself (as part of minimizing free energy (Friston, 2009)). In terms of dynamics, agonizing 5-HT2ARs leads to desynchronization and greater reverberation, forming and fostering some connections and weakening and flattening others.

There’s a lot to this, but the most relevant to our interests is the idea of relatively small changes affecting widespread neurological change that manifests in changes to higher-level processes like personality and belief.

Weaving REBUS and the Theory of Constructed Emotions together, we might be able to start getting into what a theory of meaning dynamics might look like.

For one, it cannot afford to take an eliminativist or reductionist approach—the phenomena we care about exist in and of themselves, regardless of their neurophysiological underpinnings. Both discussed views (constructive emotions and REBUS) wrestle with high-level phenomena: emotions and complex pathologies. Yet they also stay rooted in both evolutionary and information theory. Emotions are ubiquitous and pervasive enough in our thoughts and words that it would be extremely surprising to discover they served no purpose or that they could have readily been replaced by more robust and simple-to-evolve functions—at least at the level of complexity we occupy. Psychedelics, while wild and great fun to discuss and explore, are also evidently capable of effecting long-term psychological transformation. Yet they cannot be reduced to simple panacea—we do not simply take them and cure our anxiety/depression/addiction/PTSD as though these were Brave New World’s soma[4]. Instead, taking them induced a particular kind of altered state that leads to widespread, enduring mental changes—seemingly dependent on set, setting, onset, peak, and post-peak experiences—all in addition to the short-lived changes to our 5-HT2ARs. A reductionist approach to this would greatly limit our insight (though reductionism in the space is still quite mainstream—there are multiple high-profile efforts to produce psychedelics with no apparent inducement of altered states).

When it comes to modeling meaning dynamics, we also cannot afford to further subdivide concepts. For example, it is often believed that happiness and meaning (in the meaning of life) sense are the same thing. Yet happiness smuggles in several non-useful assumptions: that life ought to be aspirationally good, that everyone wants to have as much of it as possible, that there is a unified account of it, and that its absence is itself unhappiness. Meaning in life need not make such assumptions. Like constructed emotions, meaning in life can instead bind itself to survival and flourishing, to relatively straightforward informational principles that use it to some ultimately valuable end. And like REBUS, meaning in life can describe a series of acute, contextually sensitive changes that lead to an overall change in dynamics that is at least a bit predictable—if we’re careful.

Meaning, fast and slow

Meaning—in the meaning of/in life sense—is a dynamical process. Across societies and cultures, we find a curious obsession with some ultimate sense of meaning. What is the meaning of life? The universe? My life? These questions are often taken to be rhetorical. Science—in its earnest solemnity—would of course respond that the universe and everything in it has no fundamental meaning. Everything that is and ever was is just the result of particles and patterns that have no intention. Meaning is a human-level construct. And this of course is a perfectly rational stance from a dispassionate, practical, logical perspective. Any meaning we examine and model must be understood to be relative to organisms on the order of human organization and complexity. As is the case with emotions, the further we stray from humans and the cognitive tools we wield, the less certain we should feel that our intuitions about the nature of consciousness apply.

There are at least two[5] different senses of meaning in life. One is the one we’ve been discussing here—the meaning in life sense, which I will call narrative meaning. This is the purpose or direction that we believe our life serves. In a way, this narrative meaning is an optimistic, self-fulfilling prophecy that shapes our day-to-day experiences. I get up and go to work not just because the work makes me feel good, but because I believe there’s some purpose in it. And while I do plenty of things that don’t directly contribute to my meaningful goals and dreams, it’s not that difficult to reframe most of my actions in terms of my ultimate (narrative) sense of meaning[6].

Narrative meaning

Narrative meaning is non-static. Its construction changes with changes to self, friends, age, culture, location, and so on. This shift is not often noticed, as it is subtle and taken as self-evident. What I care about is that which is worthy of being cared about—and if I stop caring about it, it must not be that important. This concept is expressed in Heidegger’s concept of authenticity, which attaches positive virtues to the pursuit of one’s meaning. To him, there’s a particular set of attributes that can lead one towards this authentic end—perseverance, integrity, clear-sightedness, flexibility, and openness—all of these and more are virtues that we can cultivate throughout life if we want to be as authentic as possible (Okrent, 1993).

This authenticity is a subtype of Heidegger’s conceptualization of care. We (Dasein) find ourselves in a world that matters to us. Our moods (or dispositions) shape the world we find ourselves in. This world is constructed from past (thrownness/disposedness), future (projection/understanding), and present (fallen-ness/fascination). Heidegger’s particular terms (roughly) break down as follows:

  • Thrownness: the experience of finding yourself in a world that means something to you
  • Projection: the culturally shaped possibilities that shape the way you inhabit the world
  • Fallenness: how you actually find yourself living in the world[7]

These three aspects of care–past, future, and present–are a dynamic process. The way we experience the world as meaningful (thrownness) shapes our experiences of the possibilities (projection) available to us. In practice, we limit the scope of these possibilities (fallenness) and instead follow a narrow track of experience as we move through time and space. While Heidegger’s terms and explanations are far from straightforward, they at least demonstrate philosophy’s more formal interest in wrestling with the complex, dynamical, meaning-filled process that shapes human experience.

Returning to our conceptualization, narrative meaning is not a sterile essence but is instead a dynamic construction, similar to an emotion. What is it constructed from? In the case of emotions, these were affect and context, including language and culture. Narrative meaning is similar but not the same. It is highly language and culture sensitive. And it is sensitive to my interoceptive feelings at the moment of construction, but there’s also a memory and imagination-driven aspect. When I am asked to construct narrative meaning (e.g., explicitly, someone asks me what I’m doing living where I’m living), I take several things into account when constructing my response—without necessarily being aware of most of this process. I take stock of how things seem to be going. I also do a bit of comparison. Am I doing well according to how I think I should be doing? How have I been doing? How will I be doing once X happens? Of course, most of this is hidden from me and sometimes I will automatically respond without consideration (as most do when people ask “how are you doing?”). But somehow this question of meaning makes perfect sense no matter where or who or when I am—I can answer it sincerely because it is being asked and answered throughout my life, though it is not always easy to answer. In the case of severe depression, the answer that asserts itself is often some nihilistic claim, for me or for everyone: “Life has no purpose.” Or, “Life has nothing for me.” A declaration of the absence of meaning indicates an absence of something most people take for granted—immediate meaning.

It must also be noted that narrative meaning need not be limited to an actual narrative. We need not consciously or deliberately spell out the exact narrative by which we find ourselves living. This is similar to Heidegger’s projection aspect of care. And though we have used the word “belief” to describe our attachment to narrative meaning, the kind of belief we are demonstrating is not one with which we might identify, if pressed. If I say and experience genuine conviction that I am, say, an Effective Altruist[8] but this does not manifest itself in my behavior (e.g., I donate to the Red Cross[9]), then it’s clear that my beliefs are shallow. The kind of belief I am referring to in narrative meaning is–necessarily–authentic and aligned both with my experiences and intended actions. Therefore, intentionality is a more direct indication of narrative meaning than belief (which can effectively hold little to no relevant intention, apart from social signaling). Narrative meaning refers to the feelings and intentions that drive the construction of narrative–they are not the narrative itself. Narrative meaning is a process, not a substance.

Immediate meaning

Immediate meaning is meaning in the moment, meaning that is experienced directly by us, meaning that is reflexively attached and bound to the objects that surround us. My cat is not just an instance of felis catus—a small, predatory mammal that lives in the rectangles I live in that some Homo sapiens might call a “house”. I see my cat as special and unique. Seeing my cat is a different experience than seeing a different cat. Similarly, if I were to gift you a rock and tell you I got it in Scotland from a sheep farmer I met whilst traveling the highlands, you would find that rock more immediately meaningful than if I handed you a rock and told you it came from my backyard. The objects that surround us—in addition to having superficial features like shininess and color—have a wide array of other features. Some of these are captured in the concept of affordances, the “the quality or property of an object that defines its possible uses or makes clear how it can or should be used” (Gibson, 1969). We could say that the immediate meaning of a particular object can be reduced to its potential function. However, that’s not aligned with how meaning is experienced. It doesn’t feel as though the special warmth I feel towards my cat or the fraternal affinity you feel towards my Scottish rock are the mere experience of the functional features of each object. And this also doesn’t speak to the individual differences at the heart of these experiences. While it may be tempting to approach meaning in strictly immediately causal terms, doing so would fail to capture and explore the ways in which meaning dynamics express themselves over time. In fact, even the concept of an affordance only makes sense when we combine it with meaning.

If an affordance is “the quality or property of an object that defines its possible uses or makes clear how it can or should be used”, meaning immediately asserts itself:

  • What is an object? Something that is perceived to be an object.
  • How can an object be used? In a way that is useful to an agent.
  • How should an object be used? In a way that affects an agent.

Experience can (presumably) be stripped from affordance as defined here. However, this version of affordance–where there is no experience–is stiff and brittle. The actions an object can perform are limited, the goals of the agent are constrained, and any change to the environment will require a shift in perception and use. Similar to how meaning in language is more than symbols and shapes, affordance is about more than objects and features–even if it does not appear this way at first. Affordances smuggle in intentionality as a matter of relevance. Objects only present themselves as having affordances in light of our having long-term narrative interest in them, and this long-term narrative interest in them is in part shaped by our immediate experiences of them. To us, the world is full of objects, and these objects all carry immediate meaning.

Awe

Immediate meaning, though difficult to examine abstractly, drives high-level behavior… or does it? Aside from affordances, is there a way to reduce immediate meaning to smaller parts? Perhaps. Much of what I have been describing as “immediate meaning” is lumped into the broader, nebulous category of emotion. For instance, Keltner et al. describe awe as an emotion that shares a striking number of similarities to immediate meaning.

To Keltner, awe is marked by two features: vastness, and need for _accommodation _(Keltner & Haidt, 2003). Awe is further flavored by five additional themes: threat, beauty, ability, virtue, and supernatural causality. These themes—when present—generate and shape the experience of awe. While it’s beyond the scope of our interests here to do a deep comparison to immediate meaning, we can still critically examine this particular awe concept.

First, it is problematic to consider awe to be an emotion, at least from the classic emotion view. Indeed, Keltner recognizes this: “One reason psychologists have devoted so little attention to awe may be that it has not yet been shown to have a distinctive facial expression.” Keltner avoids this concern by working around the edges. Searching for somewhere in psychology that awe has seen any representation, he finds Maslow’s 25 features of _peak experiences _(Maslow, 1964). Awe is among the emotions associated with these experiences, alongside wonder, reverence, humility, and surrender. Relevant to our interests, Maslow states that—during peak experiences—reality is perceived with “truth, goodness, beauty, wholeness, aliveness, uniqueness, perfection, completion, justice, simplicity, richness, effortlessness, playfulness, self-sufficiency”. These perceptual features are strikingly similar to those we would expect from immediately meaningful objects and relations.

While Keltner’s work on awe is comparable to what we’re doing here with immediate meaning, its attachment to emotion theory holds it back. Awe, among other oddball emotions, is not a great fit for mainstream emotion theory. This is partly because awe is (especially) difficult to track down in expressions and brain scans and partly because talking about awe requires an expanded set of conceptual tools and instruments. Awe cannot be meaningfully reduced to a change in galvanic skin response or a class of facial expressions, yet it is perfectly coherent to talk about in folk psychological terms. So too are both narrative and immediate senses of meaning. This was recognized by the continental/existential philosophical tradition, but these have mostly remained separated from the analytic philosophy-friendly mainstream work of psychology and neuroscience, which emphasizes subjects, objects, and objective truth as forming the basis of reality, with consciousness and chaos serving as annoying stumbling blocks.

Dynamics of meaning

I propose we think of immediate meaning and narrative meanings as a pair of highly interrelated processes that constitute an emergent, dynamic process of meaning generation. At the heart of this process are the agent (us) and the environment (constructed from learning and experience)–these interact in a particular way to generate goals and the desire to pursue them.

Immediate meaning

Immediate meaning—in the moment, apparent, reflexive, direct experience—is what we experience as we move around in the world[10]. Information flows into us through our sensory organs and internal processes. Part of processing this information flow involves attaching meaning to the objects and relationships we construct. Immediate meaning is therefore both experienced and learned, alongside our other learnings. It is experientially notable when we are exposed to something that doesn’t fit our mental models—otherwise, it goes unnoticed unless specifically attended to. Each instance of immediate meaning comes with different degrees of intensity and qualities. Leaning on Maslow’s description of peak experiences (what I consider to be experiences marked by their abundance of meaning), immediate meaning involves experiencing objects and relationships as having varying levels of “truth, goodness, beauty, wholeness, aliveness, uniqueness, perfection, completion, justice, simplicity, richness, effortlessness, playfulness, self-sufficiency” attached to them (Maslow, 1964). This also means that immediate meaning can be notably absent. Such absence is well-captured by placing the word “just” in front of a description of an object. My cat is “just” a cat and my mother is instead “just” my mother or—even more abstractly “just” a Homo sapiens that happened to have given birth to me, another Homo sapiens.

This concrete-to-abstract pulling apart is often encountered in depression. Where once I looked forward to eating my favorite dessert (banana cream pie), I no longer find myself caring about this “pile of empty calories”. Even more telling are the many disturbing accounts of schizophrenia that involve objects themselves being pulled apart into smaller abstractions:

For me, madness was definitely not a condition of illness; I did not believe that I was ill. It was rather a country, opposed to Reality, where reigned an implacable light, blinding, leaving no place for shadow; an immense space without boundary, limitless, flat; a mineral, lunar country, cold as the wastes of the North Pole. In this stretching emptiness, all is unchangeable, immobile, congealed, crystallised. Objects are stage trappings, placed here and there, geometric cubes without meaning.

People turn weirdly about, they make gestures, movements without sense; they are phantoms whirling on an infinite plain, crushed by the pitiless electric light. And I—I am lost in it, isolated, cold, stripped purposeless under the light (Sechehaye, 1951).

Here, not only are perceived objects stripped bare of their immediate meaning but so too are the behaviors of people impossible to fully comprehend without this meaning. Another account is as follows:

I perceived a statue, a figure of ice which smiled at me. And this smile, showing her white teeth, frightened me. For I saw the individual features of her face, separated from each other: the teeth, then the nose, then the cheeks, then one eye and the other (Sechehaye, 1951).

This person is described as the author’s closest friend and caretaker, yet the breaking apart of immediate meaning made a warm smile appear macabre.

These are of course extreme cases. More typically, objects gain and lose their immediate meaning with some subtlety. Everything we perceive carries some of this shifting meaning. What can cause this shift? Familiarity, for one—meaning is only notable when something has changed. Mood also alters this, as do fatigue, hunger, and stress. These all affect the overall experience of objects and their relationships.

Feelings of being

Ratcliffe presents a similar concept to ours–Feelings of being. While philosophers have argued that bodily feelings are unintentional (that is, not directed at or about anything), perceptions/expressions of bodily states, and consciously experienced (C. Solomon, 2004), Ratcliffe presents a more process-oriented view (Ratcliffe, 2005):

(1) Bodily feelings are part of the structure of intentionality. They contribute to how one’s body and or aspects of the world are experienced._

(2) There is a distinction between the location of a feeling and what that feeling is of. A feeling can be in the body but of something outside the body. One is not always aware of the body, even though that is where the feeling occurs.

(3) A bodily feeling need not be an object of consciousness. Feelings are often that through which one is conscious of something else.

Immediate meaning shares these attributes–it is about both the world and the body, often goes unattended, and shapes the experience of the objects and relationships we have. This similarity ought not to be surprising: immediate meaning is a feeling of being–the difference is merely an emphasis on understanding how immediate meaning interacts with narrative meaning. This means that most of what Ratcliffe argues for in The Feeling of Being and related work applies here, particularly his arguments regarding pathological alterations to these feelings in depression, anxiety, Cotard delusion, Capgras syndrome, and schizophrenia. Roughly, the central claim is this: a breakdown in feelings of being (where immediate meaning is understood to be an aspect of these) leads to and exacerbates the development of these pathologies.

Meaning and the fringe

Another line of thinking is found in Mangan’s work on consciousness, fringe, and aesthetics. In this, Mangan brings together William James’s conceptualization of consciousness and combines it with meaning–tied strongly to the sense in which objects appear to us as being meaningful beyond the sum of their parts. Here, consciousness is described as having a two part structure: “One part consists of distinct contents, the other of vague and peripheral experiences or feelings. Meaningfulness only lives in the

second, vague aspect of consciousness” (B. B. Mangan, 1991). The first part is what James referred to (among other things–he was poetic) as the nucleus, the center of experience (B. Mangan, 2007). This is described as what we perceive with our senses–a high-resolution stream of information with definite features and feelings attached to it. The second part is called the “fringe”. The fringe consists of the indefinite and peripheral, supporting the nucleus. Mangan describes this as “context”. Our experiences (while awake and aware) have a central and definite and clear quality, but indefinite context undergirds each of them. Such context is noticed in its absence and is subsumed by the focus in its presence. Meaningfulness, as a denizen of the fringe, is therefore subject to augmentation and attenuation. Moreover, fringe contents have an additional property of being partially available to more direct and distinct attention in the consciousness-accessible nucleus. Meaningfulness is therefore implied to be directly accessible through thought.

Are Mangan’s Meaningfulness and our immediate meaning the same? Yes, roughly. Though–as was with the case with Ratcliffe–our emphasis is on the dynamics between narrative and immediate meaning. Mangan’s Meaningfulness is conceptualized as a fit to James’s nucleus-fringe framework. To wit, Mangan says this of Meaningfulness (B. B. Mangan, 1991):

…all of Meaningfulness' functions are applications of a single function: to signal context-fit. At base, Meaningfulness signals nothing except the degree of coherence or compatibility between a given content in consciousness and its appropriate nonconscious context.

This is a strong statement–Meaningfulness only serves one goal: context-fitting. And the experiential richness of Meaningfulness is described as a single thing: a signal[11].

These strong claims lead to another one: “..._to maximize Meaningfulness in consciousness is to increase the integration of conscious and nonconscious information”. _Therefore, Meaningfulness can be modulated by increasing the integration of the nucleus and fringe aspects of consciousness. In principle, as long as we can feel empirically comfortable with current tools that purport to study meaning (such as the Meaning in Life Questionnaire), we ought to be able to test this claim. Can Meaningfulness be increased by integrating conscious and nonconscious information? Yes, assuming we can develop an instrument that integrates this information.

Narrative meaning

What is demanded of man is not, as some existential philosophers teach, to endure the meaninglessness of life, but rather to bear his incapacity to grasp its unconditional meaningfulness in rational terms (Frankl, 1962).

Narrative meaning is the goals that drive our behavior at a high level. Though it is ultimately adaptive—narrative meaning leads to action that allows for survival, reproduction, and flourishing—it ought not to be reduced to its utility. While an outside observer might say my lifelong passion for tennis is just a manifestation of my desire for friends and exercise, I certainly do not experience it that way. Frankl, an influential existentialist, agrees: “Confounding the dignity of man with mere usefulness arises from conceptual confusion that in turn may be traced back to the contemporary nihilism transmitted on many an academic campus and many an analytical couch” (Frankl, 1962).

Narrative meaning is not a single ultimate goal but is instead a shifting constellation of goals that interact with each other and change as our environments change. And though we don’t always do this directly, it is perfectly coherent to ask anyone in any culture in any language what they want out of life. When I get up in the morning, I don’t just do it because I can’t sleep anymore or because I feel the need to forage for food—I do it because I need to do it in order to do something else. And when asked about, I can provide an earnest account of my underlying motivations.

Narrative meaning changes across time and situation. For example, we find that conservative beliefs (themselves laden with meaning statements such as “family is the most important thing in the world”) are somewhat predictable at scale, given population density and availability of resources (“Can Population Density Predict Voting Preference?,” 2015). Yet, there is a great deal of variation within these patterns. The context with which Frankl observed meaning and suffering in Man’s Search for Meaning was as a Holocaust captive. Here he considered and contrasted the varying ways with which others dealt with their horrible situation:

Dostoevsky said once, "There is only one thing I dread: not to be worthy of my sufferings." These words frequently came to my mind after I became acquainted with those martyrs whose behavior in camp, whose suffering and death, bore witness to the fact that the last inner freedom cannot be lost. It can be said that they were worthy of the their sufferings; the way they bore their suffering was a genuine inner achievement. It is this spiritual freedom—which cannot be taken away—that makes life meaningful and purposeful (Frankl, 1962).

This hints that there may be dispositional and/or strategic ways of constructing narrative meaning, regardless of environmental particulars. If an abundance of narrative meaning is dispositional, it could be that some are simply more or less inclined to reflect in this way. And if narrative meaning is strategic, it can be understood and learned. Both ideas hold water. Frankl seems to have believed the same. As a result of his experiences and learnings, Frankl established a line of psychotherapy entitled “logotherapy”—literally, logic-based therapy. The hope was that logotherapists could help walk their patients through a process of using logic to reframe semantically similar events. For example, if my old dog (Fido) dies and I’m beside myself with grief, asking myself “why me?” or “why Fido?” questions, logotherapy would ask me to think about how this event could be used for reflection and understanding. I might instead think “Fido had a great life—he wasn’t able to do most of what he enjoyed in the end, but I’m glad we were able to spend this time together”. This is (equally) technically true and more importantly, pragmatic. Someone who has learned to generate effective-yet-honest reframings will be able to handle adverse events much better than those who cannot—or so logotherapy claims. Regarding narrative meaning, logotherapy seems like one of potentially many tools to help alter the narrative.

Narrative meaning requires access to language and culture—without these, it is not possible to carry the kind of complex, long-term goal-driven information that is required. This claim is similar to Barrett’s non-intuitive constructed emotions theory claim: non-human animals do not have emotions, on account of their lack of complex language and culture. That isn’t to say that experience is exclusive to humans, but that meaningful experience is greatly limited in other animals, as it is missing a narrative aspect. In our framing, non-human animals may be able to have a flavor of immediate meaning and goal-driven behavior, but this would be simpler and lack some of the qualitative features human meaning has.

Combining immediate and narrative meaning

image2

Figure 2 - Direct comparison of the two meaning processes

The central thesis here is that immediate and narrative senses of meaning are interdependent in humans and that their interactions are–in principle–predictable and controllable with adequate understanding. Both senses of meaning are central to our lives, yet this has not led to a formal line of research exploring their dynamics. How does a chronic absence of immediately meaningful experience lead to a change in meaning in life narrative meaning? How strongly can changes to narrative affect immediate experience? The answers to these questions will only be found once we commit to asking them, without reducing them to insubstantial proxies[12].

Let’s explore some surface-level dynamics: immediate meaning is affected by mood, familiarity, hunger, and stress, but it is more widely affected by shifts to narrative meaning. Narrative meaning is constructed from immediate meaning. Without immediate meaning, there could be no narrative meaning. The reverse is not true. Immediate meaning does not require narrative. However, without narrative meaning, immediate meaning would be far less dynamic and reaching in its behavioral outputs. Indirect evidence for this is found in non-human animals. These appear to have kinds of experience above and beyond the most literal kind—non-human animals show strong preferences for the friendly and familiar. While we unfortunately cannot verify this directly[13], if we think that the ubiquitous way in which humans perceive a world full of immediately meaningful objects is adaptive, it would be surprising if non-human animals were devoid of immediately meaningful experience. This argument might be thought to apply to the narrative sense of meaning. Long-term goal-attainment can be helped through narrative meaning. But this requires the powers of language and culture. Non-human animals do of course show signs of having long-term goals (e.g., squirrels hiding acorns, beavers building housing), but these are extremely stubborn and brittle and limited to just a few per species, even the cleverest ones. The dynamic flexibility—both with regard to task and time—requires the high-level abstraction afforded us by language and culture.

Briefly, then, immediate meaning is affected by various factors but can shift strongly as narrative meaning shifts. Narrative meaning is much more sensitive to immediate meaning. For us to feel like our life has purpose, it is necessary that this life—through memory and experience—furnish immediately meaningful instances. The statement “my life has meaning” only makes sense if this statement is made by a person who has had/can have immediately meaningful experiences. Though individuals who are undergoing difficult circumstances might be able to “see the silver lining”, this often feels unnatural, even forced. Recall the schizophrenia accounts: “Objects are stage trappings, placed here and there, geometric cubes without meaning” and “People turn weirdly about, they make gestures, movements without sense”. A world where this is the norm would almost certainly fail to provide the conditions necessary for producing narrative meaning. This can in part account for why people with severe depression—marked by in-the-moment apathy and disconnection, indications of lost immediate meaning—tend to produce nihilistic statements about narrative meaning: “Life has no purpose”, “What’s the point of living?”, and “Nobody wants me here”. These statements are typical of severe depression and reveal the strong connection between immediate and narrative meaning. Without directly meaningful experience, we cannot readily produce meaningful narrative.

Going in the other direction, we find that there’s still some connection between the two senses of meaning but that their relationship is different. If I believe my purpose is to be a baker and this leads me to take actions to become one, these actions could well lead me to immediately meaningful experiences. In a way, this is a self-fulfilling prophecy. I think that I want something and that shapes my experience of working towards that thing—each step feels especially meaningful insofar as I know it aligns with my narrative ends. (This echoes Heidegger’s care concept.) Of course, I might find along the way that I don’t actually enjoy the work of being a baker as much as I enjoyed the idea of being a baker. This separation of narrative and immediate meaning can lead to existential concerns. If I build my identity around the achievement of some goal and find the steps along the way onerous, then this can be, at minimal, genuinely concerning. At worst, it can trigger an existential crisis—or even lead to depression. It seems, then, that trying to keep the dynamics between immediate and narrative meanings healthy will involve efforts to keep the two in relative harmony. If I aspire to be something I actually have a hope of being (scientist, good father, monk) instead of something I will almost certainly never be (US President, prima ballerina, Pope), I might be able to avoid the backlash as reality crashes against immediate meaning. Just as importantly, aspiring to be something I can be is more likely to lead me to immediately aligned experiences. The journey matters just as much as the destination–though an absence of destination (built through narrative meaning) will constrain the range of possible experience. Goal-driven narrative compels us to change our situation, which in turn enables the generation of immediately meaningful experience.

We find many examples of this dual-aspect meaning process in religion, though Eastern and Western emphasis usually leads to favoring one over the other. In Christian circles, the emphasis is often on narrative meaning, spelled out explicitly in terms of ultimate purpose or meaning: “And this is eternal life, that they know you, the only true God, and Jesus Christ whom you have sent” (John 17:3). There’s some care for individual experiences—sin only makes sense if we treat it as something that accumulates over time—but most modern Christian sects place stronger emphasis on long-term goals. In Buddhist circles, meaning comes from learning to overcome our desires. While there is an ultimate goal—enlightenment—this is attained through focus on overcoming and managing each moment. The dedication to managing individual experience is manifest in meditative practices that follow Buddhism, which teach practitioners to actively pull themselves away from narrative meaning in favor of intentionally focusing on the experience of each moment. Still, all persistent religions deal with both senses of meaning as a matter of fundamental doctrine and practice.

Another place to notice meaning is in the previously mentioned peak experiences described by Maslow and others. Some events seem to trigger altered states that are marked by their meaningfulness, both in the moment and upon reflection. In terms of behavior, these are recognized by the following symptoms (Maslow, 1964):

  • Loss of judgment to time and space
  • The feeling of being one whole and harmonious self, free of dissociation or inner conflict
  • The feeling of using all capacities and capabilities at their highest potential, or being "fully functioning"
  • Functioning effortlessly and easily without strain or struggle
  • Feeling completely responsible for perceptions and behavior. Use of self-determination to becoming stronger, more single-minded, and fully volitional
  • Being without inhibition, fear, doubt, and self-criticism
  • Spontaneity, expressiveness, and naturally flowing behavior that is not constrained by conformity
  • A free mind that is flexible and open to creative thoughts and ideas
  • Complete mindfulness of the present moment without influence of past or expected future experiences
  • A physical feeling of warmth, along with a sensation of pleasant vibrations emanating from the heart area outward into the limbs

Though a bit conceptually squishy, this description of peak experience ought to look familiar with regard to our conceptualization of meaning. More strongly, we say that peak experiences are meaningful experiences, both immediately and narratively speaking. If this is true, a careful examination of peak experiences could lead to us understanding the dynamics of meaning.

Self and meaning

We mentioned that meaning has intentionality–both senses of meaning have an aboutness. Immediate meaning is our feelings in the world, of the world (including our own body). It is also–per Mangan–a signal of context fit. Both of these framings hold us as a singular, uniform organism at the center and that which is immediately meaningful is meaningful in light of there being a single entity (us) that cares about its fate. This caring manifests itself subtly most of the time. When I feel tired, I don’t have to think that the feeling of being tired is directed towards anything in particular–both “I am tired” and the “feeling of being tired” blend together. This mostly goes unnoticed. Though I–a complex organism–am driven by allostasis, this low-level goal does not surface itself directly. I can reason about my feelings (why do I feel tired?) and supply narrative around this feeling (because I am hungry), but a True answer to this will always elude me. The “I” at the center of this approximation through narrative is my self. There are philosophies that deny the fundamental reality of an “I” at the center of experience, but experience only can be made sense of if there is an experiencer at the center of it. Feelings in the world can be made sense of when I believe that they are real and undeniable–to question my own experiences would be to question the only tools with which I have a hope of interacting with the world–my senses and my knowledge.

Both immediate and narrative meaning make use of the self (i.e., the implicit “I”). Immediate meaning needs the self to form the Jamesian nucleus to consciousness. Reality unfolds in a smooth, continuous, and coherent fashion around a center.[14] This is of course almost completely transparent to the experiencer. When I am hungry, I simply experience hunger and know that it is me who is hungry. Or at least I can assume it is me who is hungry–it is (perhaps) surprisingly straightforward to fool us into having an experience on behalf of other people, animals, or even objects[15]. Our self can readily blend into other apparent selves (Safdari Sharabiani, 2021).

Narrative meaning–unlike immediate meaning–has the self in the foreground. I care about my life and the lives of those who I care about. Even altruistic narratives have a self at the center. I want to help the less fortunate. This wanting may not come from my belief that it will benefit me in any way, but I could not want any particular outcome unless I identify as a human that could have such desires. This tension has concerned theologians of all backgrounds (“can one be truly good?”, “can one cast off all desires?”). But, as a matter of definitional coherence, narrative meaning necessarily entails a desiring, goal-driven self.

Given the presence of self in both immediate and narrative meanings, understanding the dynamics between them ought to entail a study and consideration of the self and the roles it plays.

Environment

Environment shapes immediate and narrative meaning just as much as they shape each other. The environment includes dynamically changing language and culture. The construction of meaning rests on the assumed existence and connection between our self and the other selves, real or imagined[16].

The thing that’s most constant is change–environment is that which produces changes to immediate meaning and shapes the development of narrative meaning. Another thing to note is that the existence and reality of other selves is secondary to the force they exert on our self. We are deeply social, leading our relationships to drive our narratives. Every narrative meaning can be straightforwardly reframed as a social narrative. Even if I (as a friend of mine does) find solving Rubix cubes as quickly as possible deeply enjoyable, I would still find myself comparing my score to others so involved. And even if no one were left besides me, I would still find myself comparing my current self with a memory of my past self or a projection of a potential self who is better than I currently am. The social narrative is flexible and accommodating. While we often try to distill human motivation into simple and straightforward factors (wealth, health, sex, etc.), the level of narrative that we live in is far more complex and variegated than these reductions.

It’s worth noting again that the narrative I give in response to a question of narrative meaning (e.g., “why do you solve Rubix cubes?”) is not, logically speaking, True. That is, when I give you any account as to why I did anything, this should be considered an assertion of belief, not truth. This belief should also be understood to be a snapshot at best–a small change to my mind or the environment can result in a different narrative response. Whatever I think of in response to the question will be constructed in the moment and expressed in imperfect language and therefore non-identical with some “objectively true” statement of meaning. Any explicit narrative we provide should instead be understood to be an informative construction. It gives indirect hints (to me and to everyone else) as to what is driving my behavior at a high level. Narrative meaning is dynamic and changing. This isn’t to say that it is useless–it’s still informative and still helps us make predictions about experience and behavior.

When I say my life is meaningful, I tell you something different then when I say my life has no meaning. And you learn something different when I struggle to answer the question at all. Narrative meaning is therefore best understood in context. Can the narrative be generated? How strongly do I feel that my life has meaning? Do other lives have meaning? Moreover, we can still investigate behavioral proxies. Do I hesitate and shift my eyes around when asked about meaning? Does my heart rate rise? Is my amygdala excited? We can even imagine tracking other related metrics–does someone who reports high meaning in life find arbitrary connections between things easier to form? Are people high in religiosity more likely to attribute intentionality to the arbitrary placement of wooden blocks[17]? There are myriad methods with which we can investigate meaning and environment once we commit to trying to investigate meaning for its own sake.

image3

Figure 3 - Meaning dynamics - Immediate meaning gives context to narrative meaning; narrative meaning alters the environment and gives a backdrop for immediate meaning, which is additionally influenced by a variety of contextual factors. Self is shaped by the environment and leads to changes in the environment.

Modeling meaning

Now that we’ve discussed the aspects and relationships of meaning, we can more formally describe our proposed model.

On one side, we have immediate meaning:

  • Reflexive experience of objects and relations between objects as being meaningful.
  • The integration of conscious and nonconscious information
  • Constructed from sensory organs and internal processes
  • Learned (much in the same way as we learn to identify the physical properties and affordances of the objects in our world)
  • Made attentionally salient through changes to information integration
  • Accompanied by phenomenological properties (meaningful objects feel true, good, beautiful, whole, alive, unique, perfect, complete, just, simple, and rich)
  • Affected by mood, fatigue, hunger, and stress
  • Undergirded by self and intentionality
  • Greatly impacted by narrative meaning

On the other side, we have narrative meaning:

  • Purposeful, goal-driven thoughts and behavior over potentially long periods of time, throughout complex, shifting environments.
  • Constructed through language and cultural cues, as well as memories and immediately meaningful experiences.
  • Dependent on the development of language and culture (non-human animals do not have it[18])
  • Motivational—narrative meaning drives our actions
  • Notable in its abundance or absence
  • Self at the center of most constructions (and still present in all other constructions)
  • Construction depends on memories or experiences of immediate meaning (there can be no narrative meaning without immediate meaning).

The relationship between the two meanings is as follows:

  • Immediate meaning is shaped by narrative meaning
  • As our environment changes, so too does our narrative meaning, which in turn leads to shifts to our immediate meaning.
  • Changes to our self changes both our immediate and narrative appraisals, both directly and through downstream effects these exert on our environment.
  • An absence or abundance of immediate feedback adjusts narrative meaning

This process often goes unnoticed but can be observed as the dynamics shift. In some pathologies—namely, depression and schizophrenia—the inability to close the meaning loop manifests itself in experientially and behaviorally deleterious ways. On the other end, peak experiences describe an especially strong meaning dynamic, where conscious and nonconscious information blend together and lead to (potentially) long-term shifts to narrative meaning.

This is the rough model—testing and refining it is something else entirely. As depression and peak experiences are relatively accessible, we might look at them as pragmatic guides to understanding meaning.

The second part will be a discussion of Pivotal Mental States and peak experiences. We are using our understanding of these to design a series of experiments on measuring meaning in the face of stimuli meant to gently induce peak experiences. I will describe the pilot experiment in detail, as well as some promising directions we can take richer versions of the experimental setting.

Part 2: Experimentation

Current methods of quantifying meaning

Meaning in life research has a limited experimental background. Between psychology and anthropology, the current gold standard is to wield one of several questionnaires[19] designed to capture meaning–particularly, narrative meaning[20]. Ward and King (2016) ran three studies that used the Meaning in Life Questionnaire to see how reported meaning interacts with income and positive affect. This questionnaire has 10 questions that ask respondents to rate how well each statement applies to them–these include “I understand my life has meaning” and “I am searching for meaning in my life”. Ward and King found the following:

  • Those with high positive affect reported similar meaning in life, regardless of income
  • Those with low positive affect reported higher meaning in life with higher income
  • Without affect manipulation, higher income correlated with higher meaning in life (but this went away once affect was manipulated
  • When asked to imagine how meaningful they would find their lives in the future, the wealthy projected having more meaning in life than the poor (where the most unhappy were the most poor)

A few small lessons can be learned from this and other similar studies. For one, this supports the assumption that mood plays an outsized role in the construction of narrative meaning instances. Another lesson is that environment helps form the background of these appraisals. The wealthy–without overt manipulation–reported more meaning in life, on average. An unspoken lesson is also found in the dataset: these kinds of high-level, large samples are replete with exceptions: there were many poor who had lives brimming with meaning and many wealthy with low meaning. Such variation should not escape our notice–if there are other mediating factors that do not show up with large, clinical sampling methods, we ought to investigate them.

Reflect on people in your own life with similar backgrounds–would you expect that they’d all score similarly to each other when posed these questions? You would not–there’s more to meaning than background and affect. Nor would we expect to score the same throughout our own lives. These variations and shifts are what most interest us here. Like the affect manipulation Ward and King used, we can hope to perform similar manipulations. But we need not stop there–if what we value is maximizing meaning, we ought to target an average increase to meaning in life over time. Even better, we should see whether this increase can sustain itself over longer periods of time.

Such an endeavor might require the development of new tools for exploring meaning dynamics and inducing long-term changes. These tools need not be developed in tandem but doing so allows us to cover more ground than if we focused on one over the other. Measuring meaning dynamics can benefit from stickier changes to meaning. Similarly, enduring changes to meaning can benefit from ways to measure and track these changes.

Before moving on, we should ask ourselves whether this work has been done (presumably well) by others. We already referenced Keltner and Haidt’s work (Keltner & Haidt, 2003) on awe, which has inspired a plethora of offshoots, from ethics to altered states to mindfulness (Liu et al., 2022; Thompson, 2022; Villar et al., 2022). These are interesting in that they do reference the kinds of peak experiences (Maslow, 1964) that we described as being highly meaningful, even formative. Such apotheosis experiences often lead to enduring changes in both narrative and immediate meaning (described qualitatively). An inquiry into peak experiences might therefore yield a fitting set of experimental goals that could lead to experiments that begin to explore and uncover meaning dynamics.

Meaning and psychedelics

Elsewhere, meaning in life has been examined in relation to psychedelics. Griffiths et al. (2006) administered psilocybin to volunteers in two to three sessions and asked them to rate the resulting personal meaning: “67% of the volunteers rated the experience with psilocybin to be either the single most meaningful experience of his or her life or among the top five most meaningful experiences of his or her life”. Further, “...volunteers judged the meaningfulness of the experience to be similar, for example, to the birth of a first child or death of a parent”. Such a result is striking–not just because it speaks strongly of the powers of psychedelics that they are vaunted like this–but also because it demonstrates just how strongly particularly powerful specific immediate experiences of meaning can be.

The study continues: “In written comments about their answers, the volunteers often described aspects of the experience related to a sense of unity without content (pure consciousness) and/or unity of all things”. These claims of contentlessness and unity speak to Mangan’s view on nucleus and fringe. Recall that he asserted the following: “...to maximize Meaningfulness in consciousness is to increase the integration of conscious and nonconscious information” (B. B. Mangan, 1991)_. _If Mangan is correct, maximally (immediately) meaningful experiences will be remarkably unified. The statement of content-free consciousness is also interesting. We claimed earlier that immediate meaning often goes unnoticed and that it is only when it is abundant or absent that we are compelled to attend to it. Combining this with Mangan’s view, we encounter a strange dynamic: the strongest immediate meaning is found when attention is made its strongest but then is transformed in the integration of conscious and nonconscious information. We attend strongly, then we merge the nucleus with the fringe, producing a different kind of attention[21].** **If this is true, then another tool for investigating meaning might be to focus on attention and inattention.

From Griffiths, we also get a hint that the exact content of peak (immediately meaningful) experience is not as important as the persistence of unity during and after the peak. If we deliberately pursue peak experiences, our focus should be on unity and that which comes with it:

  • Flow: Complete absorption in one’s activity (Ellis et al., 1994)
  • Loss of self as center: Separation or blurring of the experience between the mind and body[22]
  • Silencing of narrative: Dissolution of the narrative that often occupies our conscious experience
  • Connection:** **Experience of self-other and other-other as forming a unified whole

This list differs from Keltner and Haidt’s appraisals central to awe: “...perceived vastness, and a need for accommodation, defined as an inability to assimilate an experience into current mental structures” (Keltner & Haidt, 2003). Perceived vastness and need for accommodation can lead to connection, a silencing of narrative, and a loss of self–in that sense, we’re talking about something similar. The difference is that Keltner and Haidt are mixing the cause with the effect (perception of vastness → awe, need for accommodation → awe), where we are not doing so explicitly. However, we will assert something similar: increasing flow, loss of self, narrative silencing, and/or connection directly leads to immediately meaningful experiences. These factors further lead to changes to narrative meaning (since narrative meaning is constructed from immediate meaning). Though tools such as the Meaning in Life Questionnaire are rough and limited, they present a potential way to quantitatively measure the effects of altering the above factors. In short, by investigating alterations to flow, self, narrative, and connection, we might be able to use more mainstream measurement tools to tie narrative meaning to immediate meaning.

Pivotal Mental States

Elsewhere, we find work to tie meaningful instances to a unified set of stimuli. A Pivotal Mental State (PiMS) is a “hyper-plastic state aiding rapid and deep learning that can mediate psychological transformation” (Brouwer & Carhart-Harris, 2020). This state is described in terms of evolutionary function and is tethered to a proposed set of neural correlates that could (in principle) predict whether someone is in a PiMS. According to the PiMS construct, chronic and acute stress trigger an altered state that is marked by its enduring downstream effects.

“Stress” is defined here as “the body’s multi-system response to any challenge that overwhelms, or is judged likely to overwhelm, selective homeostatic response mechanisms” (Day, 2005). The emphasis on homeostasis echoes Barrett’s Theory of Constructed Emotion, where emotion is said to have developed as a way of maintaining homeostasis in a complex social world. So too are PiMSes proposed to be a natural response to the world changing, albeit in a more extreme way. The stress a soldier on the battlefield undergoes–chronically and acutely–leads to a pivotal state that forces the body to make large adjustments. On an information level, this involves enduring changes to learned priors. PTSD is therefore given to be the result of extreme environmental changes leading to a singular episode of strong rewiring. Such events are highly meaningful–changes to the system that produces immediate meaning manifest themselves in narrative meaning. For better or for worse, to someone who has served on a battlefield, the experience of doing so plays an outsized role in the remainder of that person’s life.

Brouwer and Carhart-Harris’s paper is mostly centered around considering psychedelics as an acute PiMS trigger. These are near-direct triggers: you merely provide some context (set) and the trigger (psychedelics altering 5-HT2AR serotonin receptors), resulting in a pivotal state.

PiMS presents a potential inroad to studying meaning dynamics. The exact stressor is not important so much as its properties and its downstream effects. In other words, we can invent our own PiMS trigger based on PiMS principles and expect to see similarly meaningful outcomes.

What should these triggers look like? Brouwer and Carhart-Harris define stress as a general bodily response to overwhelming challenge, but this is not specific enough to be actionable. They also name candidate triggers: psychedelics, life-or-death situations, meditation, and breathwork. Besides inducing PiMS, what is common among these? They all heavily involve aspects of peak experiences: flow, loss of self as center, silencing of narrative, and connection. Put straightly, instances of PiMS are peak experiences and PiMS (as a construct) endeavors to give an evolutionary account and to bind experience to neural and informational correlates.

Generating peak experience

Can we intentionally generate peak experiences in order to induce immediate meaning and shape narrative meaning? If the Pivotal Mental States construct holds water, the exact mechanism for generating peak experience is less important than its proximate and downstream effects. If we take psychedelics as a core example of successful peak experience production, we can lean on typical aspects of the psychedelic experience to generate mental states high in immediate meaning, integrating conscious and nonconscious information, per Mangan (1991). How do we integrate conscious and nonconscious information? By intentionally copying aspects of the psychedelic experience.

“Psychedelic” means (literally) “mind-revealing”, implying that psychedelics are revealing our own minds to our selves. This contrasts itself with the experiences themselves, which involve hallucinations and illusions of a wide variety of shapes, patterns, sounds, smells, tastes, and tactile events, as a matter of fact–all amounting to a peculiar kind of altered state. Further, the altered state is replete with meaning and the aspects of peak experiences we enumerated: flow, loss of self as center, silencing of narrative, and connection.

Our central experimental thesis is this: targeting sensory and/or qualities of peak experience (flow, etc.) will increase immediate meaning. Moreover, combining multiple meaning-increasing stimuli will have an additive effect, which, at some point, produces long-term changes to both immediate and narrative meaning.

The assertion that sensory and peak experience correlates can themselves produce usefully altered states runs counter to our understanding–we treat these correlates as side-effects resulting from psychedelics messing with our neurons:

(psychedelics → altered states + correlates of altered states)

versus

(correlates of altered states → altered states)

For example, listening to specific kinds of music–live, loud, lyrical–readily produces a compelling experience. Without this experiential feedback, music would not be interesting to us, lacking useful information. Music does not hold any intrinsic meaning[23], yet we swear by it as a common, almost ubiquitous source of meaning. Musical experiences can be more or less meaningful, shifting from dark and devastating to upbeat and profound. Even the rhythms seem to resonate with us, compelling us to move in accordance with the beat. This is explored in the musical entrainment literature, which finds that music binds and shapes both our personal and interpersonal experience in predictable yet culturally sensitive ways (Clayton et al., 2020). Here, rhythm is essential for producing entrainment, as are attention and anticipation.

image4

Figure 4 - Musical Entrainment model (Clayton et al., 2020)

Beyond music, we encounter other forms of entrainment. Brainwave entrainment syncs auditory, tactile, and visual stimuli to target specific, EEG-measurable voltage fluctuation patterns. This research is being explored as a means to treat ADHD (López, 2020), improve sleep quality (Abeln et al., 2014), and strengthen meditation (Lavallee et al., 2011). This last application is especially relevant, as meditation is associated with both peak experiences and PiMSes. Commonly, brainwave entrainment targets the theta (4-8Hz) and/or alpha (8-12Hz) frequency bands, which are found in relaxed, hypnagogic, and deep sleep states (Lavallee et al., 2011). Intentional entrainment could be a way to target the correlates of altered states, because it is uniquely positioned as a controllable, quantitative, predictable method of integrating conscious and nonconscious information.

Central to entrainment is attention–if something fails to grab our attention over time, we do not entrain. Increasing entrainment is therefore a matter of selecting stimuli that reliably arrest our attention. This is non-trivial, in that we crave change but appreciate stability. There are, however, fascinating visual and auditory stimuli that match these demands. Recreational explorers of psychedelic experiences (called “psychonauts”) have built and developed tools that enhance and shape their experiences (called “journeys”).

For the sake of the present experiment, we’re committing to inducing peak experiences through external stimuli (versus psychedelics, which directly alter neural dynamics), but the experience-shaping tools that psychonauts find endlessly fascinating are at least moderately fascinating to us, even when sober. We will single out one of these and examine whether we can use it to produce the effect we’re looking for:** immediately meaningful experience that significantly alters narrative meaning, both in the short and long-term. **

Hopalong Orbits

Form Constants

One feature common to psychedelic experiences is the perception of _form constants _(Bressloff et al., 2002). These are recurring geometric patterns that Klüver identified through self-exploration of mescaline.

image5

Figure 5 - Klüver’s Form Constants found in his exploration of mescaline (Bressloff et al., 2002)

These patterns are found in both nature and in art–from the earliest pieces (Lewis-Williams et al., 1988) to now. Psychedelic experiences involve a layering of these patterns over both direct visual experience (in the nucleus of consciousness) and in imaginings. Further investigation has shown that these are found in entoptic phenomena–our eyes capture light with physical neuronal arrays that produce form constant patterns at the lowest levels (the eyes and V1 region of the brain) (Entoptic Phenomenon - an Overview | ScienceDirect Topics, n.d.). Because of this, we might entertain several possibilities about the intrinsic interestingness of form constants:

  1. We’re always processing these patterns–they’re just suppressed (Winkelman, 2017)
  2. The patterns are intrinsically, aesthetically interesting
  3. The patterns evoke hypnagogia
  4. The patterns decrease_ functional integrity_ of the self-referencing processes in the default mode network (DMN) (R. Carhart-Harris et al., 2014)
  5. Viewing these patterns evokes past experiences of altered states

These are all candidate explanations but need not be considered independently. It could be that we are simultaneously suppressing form constants, finding them pretty, hypnotic, and evocative of past altered states. They might also show up in the brain as decreased functional integrity within and between the DMN and other regions. The bottom line is this: we find form constants both attentionally arresting and aesthetically interesting. And, fortunately, variations to these patterns can sustain our interest.

Subjective effects

Besides form constants, psychonauts widely report changes to color perception, where reds are experienced as more red and novel, indescribable shades are reported. These changes are accompanied by many more, documented in detail in a wiki format (Subjective Effect Index - PsychonautWiki, 2022). Among the most accessible and relevant are experiences of recursion, environmental patterning/cubism, and symmetrical texture repetition. These are somewhat reproducible–with 3D graphical rendering tools–it’s possible to simulate these features of psychedelic tripping, to approximate the visual features of a psychedelic trip.

Barry Martin’s Hopalong Orbits Visualizer

Barry Martin’s Hopalong Orbits Visualizer uses a relatively straightforward fractal attractor algorithm to generate recursive, patterned, repetitive patterns (Hopalong Attractor - Maple Help, n.d.):

image6

By providing a set of initial variable values and randomly shifting these each iteration, the visualizer produces a series of cartesian points that result in form constants. These are also given random colors each iteration and are made to rotate slightly and move towards the experiencer at a controllable velocity. Additionally, users may shift their perspective slightly as they experience forward movement through the simulated space.

image7

Figure 6 - Randomly generated fractal sequence, taken from Barry Martin’s Hopalong Orbit Visualizer

The orbital patterns exhibit recursion, environmental patterning/cubism, and symmetrical texture repetition, all of which are typical perceptions found in psychedelic experience. This experience also supports some of our enumerated points on form constants: They are (2) interesting, (3) hypnotic, and (5) evocative of past experiences with altered states. As for whether (1) is true–this merits further investigation. (4) might be readily verified as well–if we can demonstrate that merely observing these patterns is sufficient to acutely decrease functional integrity in the DMN, this would provide direct evidence for our proposed (correlates of altered states → altered states) model. But we need not involve brain fMRI to support this. Instead, it would be similarly compelling to use a version of the Visualizer to demonstrate the possibility of transforming sensory stimuli into altered states, marked by their immediate and narrative meaning.

The Effects of Sensory Stimulation on the Generation of Meaning

Leveraging everything discussed here, we’ve developed a pilot study to investigate the potential of generating meaning from sensory stimulus.

Tools

We are using a customized version of Barry Martin’s Hopalong Orbits Visualizer as a stimulus generator. This is written in JavaScript and leverages the Three.js graphical rendering package. Data logging is done via Google Firebase, where participant behavior is tracked over time and stored in a database. This data contains snapshots of application state, including cursor location (x-y coordinates), rotation speed, movement speed, current random number generator seed, and current hue values for the last points rendered. The generated pattern order will be the same for each participant (though the exact timings of each pattern they are exposed to may change due to their speeding up or slowing down their movement).

Participants

We are selecting participants via Mechanical Turk, a recruiting platform that lets us select for a sample based on our recruiting criteria. The inclusionary criteria are as follows:_ >= 18_ years of age, fluent English speakers, good/corrected-to-good vision, US citizens, no history of dizziness or epilepsy[24].

Experimental design

Participants will do the following:

  1. Enter their ID (so we can anonymously collate their results)
  2. Be guided through the controls–we will have them demonstrate rotation, speed, and perspective shift via keyboard input
  3. Freely explore the Visualizer for several minutes (8 minutes as a reasonable starting point[25])
  4. Respond to a series of questions (Qualtrics questionnaire embedded in Visualizer)

We will collect the following information via Qualtrics:

  • Demographics: Age, Gender
  • Belief in God/gods
  • Past experience with psychedelics
  • Meaning in life Questionnaire (in Appendix)

Control

image8

Figure 7 - Alternative Control variant of Barry Martin’s Hopalong Orbit Visualizer

We will additionally filter half of our participants into a control condition. This is a version of the Visualizer, with the following changes:

  • Instead of moving forwards, participants move backwards[26]
  • Initial speed is low
  • No rotation
  • No control over perspective or settings
  • Slight desaturation of orbit colors
  • Points are randomly +/- jittered in x-y direction

The resulting Visualizer contains the same informational content (colors, number of points, sequencing of pattern generation) but is intentionally made to be less attentionally interesting. Participants will spend the same amount of time in the control condition as the main condition, though we will omit the training sequence (as the user cannot modify their settings in the control). Our intention for the control is to limit the (2) interesting, (3) hypnotic, and (5) past experience parallels. Recursion, environmental patterning/cubism, and symmetrical texture repetition are also evaded, without presenting quantitatively different information. Instead, what ought to be different is the quality of experience.

Alternative controls are possible. We could, for example, omit the Visualizer entirely and instead show a video of something generally uninteresting (e.g., a PSA from the IRS on filing taxes). This would also fail to provide a correlate of altered states (and therefore be unlikely to produce an altered state). However, this would present quantitatively (and, likely, qualitatively) different information.

Baseline

Out of concern for the generalizability of the Mechanical Turk population, we will additionally capture a small baseline score for Meaning in Life. This can therefore be contrasted directly with the control and main conditions.

Measurement

What can be measured? We are collecting a few different data sets:

  1. Visualizer state over time
  2. Demographics/beliefs/history (post stimulus)
  3. Meaning in Life (post stimulus)

In the main (non-control) condition, the Visualizer state also contains information about participant behavior, represented as the delta between time slices. In other words, we can observe participant behavior as the delta of the controllable parameters. When they increase rotation speed, we know when this occurred and what they were viewing based on the current seed (which can reproduce the Hopalong Orbit that they were presented with, as well as the hues the Orbit was given). User behavior is not contained within the control condition, since the Visualizer they have is non-interactive–however, we can also reproduce the patterns and colors they would have been exposed to over time.

Past research on Meaning in Life has demonstrated a sensitivity to age, gender, and religious belief (Krok, 2015; Steger et al., 2006) when predicting scores. We are also capturing past psychedelic experience, as (5) would predict that attention and entrainment from form constants could be mediated by past experience with psychedelics.

Hypotheses

Main predictions:

  1. Participants exposed to the Hopalong orbit Visualizer will score higher in Meaning in Life than those exposed to both the control Visualizer and the baseline
  2. Participants exposed to the control Visualizer will score similarly in Meaning in Life to the baseline

Secondary predictions:

  1. Participates who more actively move and change their parameters in the first 3 minutes will score more highly in Meaning in Life than those who do not
  2. Participants who are more religious and/or have past experiences with psychedelics will score more highly in Meaning in Life than those who are not/have not
  3. Participants who have past experiences with psychedelics and who are high (>75%) in belief in God/gods will score highest in Meaning in Life, regardless of condition
  4. Meaning in Life will positively correlate with high (>75%) belief in God/gods
  5. Meaning in Life will positively correlate with past psychedelic usage

Further predictions (not presented as formal hypotheses):

  1. Participants will fall into a few categories: those who continue to explore, those who explore for a while but then settle, and those who do not explore at all
  2. Perspective shifting will be the predominant method of control, with rotation and speed being roughly equivalent to each other (measured as normalized percentage shift from baseline)

Future directions

There are three possibilities for main prediction 1:

  1. Positive correlation between meaning of life and exposure to non-control stimulus[27]
  2. Negative correlation between meaning of life and exposure to non-control stimulus
  3. No clear correlation between meaning of life and exposure to non-control stimulus

There are three possibilities for main prediction 2:

  1. Positive correlation between meaning of life and exposure to control stimulus
  2. Negative correlation between meaning of life and exposure to control stimulus
  3. No clear correlation between meaning of life and exposure to control stimulus

Prediction 1 is most relevant to determining next steps (though prediction 2 is important support for prediction 1).

If we find a positive correlation between stimulus exposure and Meaning in Life, this can help demonstrate the flexibility of meaning stimulus. Even though we are only involving vision and are not strongly controlling the environment[28], a proximate effect of exposure to psychedelic visuals generating measurable changes to meaning would be good support for our underlying models.

If we find a negative correlation between stimulus exposure and Meaning in Life, this could signal several things: the Visualizer did not feel good to strangers, something in the environment went wrong (e.g., inconsistent frame rate makes it jump around and induce mild nausea), the user controls led to participants choosing parameters that produced negative valence, or–Meaning in Life and psychedelic experience are simply anti-correlated. In any case, a negative correlation would be interesting and cause for reflection.

If we find an unclear correlation between stimulus exposure and Meaning in Life, this could mean several things: The chaotic environment was simply too noisy to demonstrate an effect (which is quite modest–Meaning in Life scores tend to vary by a single point on average across a sample at best, even across strong correlates like age and gender (Steger et al., 2006)). Alternatively, as is the case with a negative correlation, it could be that the Visualizer was simply too limited in this context: 8 minutes, potentially small displays and low frame rates and refresh rates, user controls unfamiliar, or the Visualizer was simply not powerful enough to elicit the (weak) peak experience by itself. Determining which of these apply will be difficult without anything to contrast our results against, but a future pilot controlling the environment more carefully (e.g., by running an offline version in a lab space on a designated computer) could help narrow down the potential variables muddying the results.

All three possibilities would help inspire future directions, but we can readily identify improvements to the experimental setup.

The pilot experiment is vision-based, but many correlates of psychedelic experiences involve other senses–touch and audition being the most notable. Given what we know about psychedelic experiences, we can predict that peak experiences (i.e., Pivotal Mental States) are more likely to be induced when we introduce additional sensory modalities (assuming our initial assumption of (correlates of altered states → altered states) holds).

Additionally, though online studies can be effective at rapidly capturing a lot of data from representative samples, they are also chaotic environments. This is as relevant as possible here, as we are trying to target flow, loss of self as center, silencing of narrative, and connection–all these involve attention and motivation, both of which are difficult to constrain in an online study. An in-person version could eliminate most of this noise.

Going down the audition route, we have many possibilities–if we continue to mirror psychedelics, the music and sounds we choose should fit those used in those studies, as they were carefully selected over many iterations as experience-enhancing (Griffiths et al., 2006). Alternatively, we could use music as a control–intentionally choosing songs that might break flow and increase narrative and self. Another possibility is exploring constrained versus unconstrained experience, where in one we choose the playlist and another we allow participants to select their own music.

Touch also allows for possibilities. There are auditory touch devices like the SubPac (SUBPAC - The New Way to Experience Sound, n.d.) that synchronize to the low tones (base) in music, producing the experienced merger of touch and sound and increasing immersion and entrainment[29]. We might also use haptic feedback from controllers or other devices and synchronize and simulate contacting objects within the Visualizer’s simulated space.

Virtual Reality (VR) and Augmented Reality (AR) could similarly increase flow and immersion through invoking presence (Immersive and Interactive Awe: Evoking Awe via Presence in Virtual Reality and Online Videos to Prompt Prosocial Behavior | Human Communication Research | Oxford Academic, n.d.). Pivotal Mental States propose that acute stress (overwhelming, or judged likely to overwhelm) is a trigger for said states (forms of peak experiences). VR and AR might provide the necessary stress to invoke these states.

On the data collection end, we should investigate ways to better capture immediate meaning. Pupil dilation, galvanic skin response, EEG, eye-tracking[30], breath tracking, and heart rate monitoring could all present predictive correlates to immediate meaning. We should also investigate connection and immediate meaning. If you are in a peak state, we should predict that you will find it easy to feel as though anything and everything is connected. This could be measured by having participants perform a sorting task to group arbitrary objects or by having them match shapes to colors–or another equivalent task that can demonstrate a heightened ability to find connections between objects and ideas in their world.

Lastly and perhaps most importantly, in order to demonstrate that immediate and narrative meaning are dynamically intertwined, we need to show that changes to meaning can be sustained over time (as opposed to being affected only during and immediately after the experiment). To do this, we should readminister our measurements over time (weeks to months later), without intentionally re-priming participants. We should expect to see a marked difference between the control and non-control. If there is a difference, we also should see some dropoff effect over time but a stabilization of performance at the tail end (i.e., a negative exponential curve shape). We can further parallel psychedelic (and meditation) studies by including multiple exposures to the stimuli over some timer period–in this case, we should expect there to be a less steep dropoff and a faster flattening of the curve (Vermetten et al., 2020).


Immediate and narrative meaning are central to our existence–more than quarks and atoms and galaxies–but we haven’t intentionally included these in our scientific discussions. There are many good reasons for this: meaning is an overloaded term, it changes constantly, and it has more apparently tractable siblings (emotion, affect, awe, etc.). That said, meaning is also completely comprehensible to everyone everywhere. We care about things and direct our lives towards the goals it presents.

Here, we have outlined meaning conceptually and have proposed a simple pilot study to identify its construction in the wild. There are many ways to approach immediate and narrative meaning–we’ve outlined just one of them.

Bibliography

Abeln, V., Kleinert, J., Strüder, H. K., & Schneider, S. (2014). Brainwave entrainment for better sleep and post-sleep state of young elite soccer players – A pilot study. _European Journal of Sport Science_, _14_(5), 393–402. [https://doi.org/10.1080/17461391.2013.819384](https://doi.org/10.1080/17461391.2013.819384) 


Barrett, L. F. (2016). The theory of constructed emotion: An active inference account of interoception and categorization. _Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience_, nsw154. [https://doi.org/10.1093/scan/nsw154](https://doi.org/10.1093/scan/nsw154) 


Barrett, L. F., Quigley, K. S., & Hamilton, P. (2016). An active inference theory of allostasis and interoception in depression. _Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences_, _371_(1708), 20160011. [https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2016.0011](https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2016.0011) 


Bressloff, P. C., Cowan, J. D., Golubitsky, M., Thomas, P. J., & Wiener, M. C. (2002). What geometric visual hallucinations tell us about the visual cortex. _Neural Computation_, _14_(3), 473–491. [https://doi.org/10.1162/089976602317250861](https://doi.org/10.1162/089976602317250861) 


Brouwer, A., & Carhart-Harris, R. L. (2020). Pivotal mental states. _Journal of Psychopharmacology_, 0269881120959637. [https://doi.org/10.1177/0269881120959637](https://doi.org/10.1177/0269881120959637) 


C. Solomon, R. (2004). _Thinking About Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions_. Oxford University Press USA.


Can population density predict voting preference? (2015, September 14). _City Monitor_. [https://citymonitor.ai/government/elections/can-population-density-predict-voting-preference-1395](https://citymonitor.ai/government/elections/can-population-density-predict-voting-preference-1395) 


Carhart-Harris, R. L., & Friston, K. J. (2019). REBUS and the Anarchic Brain: Toward a Unified Model of the Brain Action of Psychedelics. _Pharmacological Reviews_, _71_(3), 316–344. [https://doi.org/10.1124/pr.118.017160](https://doi.org/10.1124/pr.118.017160) 


Carhart-Harris, R., Leech, R., Hellyer, P., Shanahan, M., Feilding, A., Tagliazucchi, E., Chialvo, D., & Nutt, D. (2014). The entropic brain: A theory of conscious states informed by neuroimaging research with psychedelic drugs. _Frontiers in Human Neuroscience_, _8_. [https://www.frontiersin.org/article/10.3389/fnhum.2014.00020](https://www.frontiersin.org/article/10.3389/fnhum.2014.00020) 


Chiao, J. Y., Harada, T., Komeda, H., Li, Z., Mano, Y., Saito, D., Parrish, T. B., Sadato, N., & Iidaka, T. (2009). Neural basis of individualistic and collectivistic views of self. _Human Brain Mapping_, _30_(9), 2813–2820. [https://doi.org/10.1002/hbm.20707](https://doi.org/10.1002/hbm.20707) 


Clayton, M., Jakubowski, K., Eerola, T., Keller, P. E., Camurri, A., Volpe, G., & Alborno, P. (2020). Interpersonal Entrainment in Music Performance: Theory, Method, and Model. _Music Perception_, _38_(2), 136–194. [https://doi.org/10.1525/mp.2020.38.2.136](https://doi.org/10.1525/mp.2020.38.2.136) 


Crane, T., & French, C. (2021). The Problem of Perception. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), _The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy_ (Fall 2021). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. [https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2021/entries/perception-problem/](https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2021/entries/perception-problem/) 


Davis, A. K., Barrett, F. S., May, D. G., Cosimano, M. P., Sepeda, N. D., Johnson, M. W., Finan, P. H., & Griffiths, R. R. (2020). Effects of Psilocybin-Assisted Therapy on Major Depressive Disorder: A Randomized Clinical Trial. _JAMA Psychiatry_. [https://doi.org/10.1001/jamapsychiatry.2020.3285](https://doi.org/10.1001/jamapsychiatry.2020.3285) 


Day, T. A. (2005). Defining stress as a prelude to mapping its neurocircuitry: No help from allostasis. _Progress in Neuro-Psychopharmacology & Biological Psychiatry_, _29_(8), 1195–1200. [https://doi.org/10.1016/j.pnpbp.2005.08.005](https://doi.org/10.1016/j.pnpbp.2005.08.005) 


Ellis, G. D., Voelkl, J. E., & Morris, C. (1994). Measurement and Analysis Issues with Explanation of Variance in Daily Experience Using the Flow Model. _Journal of Leisure Research_, _26_(4), 337–356. [https://doi.org/10.1080/00222216.1994.11969966](https://doi.org/10.1080/00222216.1994.11969966) 


_Entoptic Phenomenon—An overview | ScienceDirect Topics_. (n.d.). Retrieved May 27, 2022, from [https://www.sciencedirect.com/topics/medicine-and-dentistry/entoptic-phenomenon](https://www.sciencedirect.com/topics/medicine-and-dentistry/entoptic-phenomenon) 


Frankl, V. E. (Viktor E., 1905-1997 author. (1962). _Man’s search for meaning: An introduction to logotherapy_. A newly revised and enlarged edition of From death-camp to existentialism. Boston : Beacon Press, 1962. [https://search.library.wisc.edu/catalog/999542555202121](https://search.library.wisc.edu/catalog/999542555202121) 


Friston, K. (2009). The free-energy principle: A rough guide to the brain? _Trends in Cognitive Sciences_, _13_(7), 293–301. [https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2009.04.005](https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2009.04.005) 


Gibson, J. (1969). The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems. _The Art Bulletin_, _51_(3), 310–311. [https://doi.org/10.1080/00043079.1969.10790296](https://doi.org/10.1080/00043079.1969.10790296) 


Griffiths, R. R., Richards, W. A., McCann, U., & Jesse, R. (2006). Psilocybin can occasion mystical-type experiences having substantial and sustained personal meaning and spiritual significance. _Psychopharmacology_, _187_(3), 268–283. [https://doi.org/10.1007/s00213-006-0457-5](https://doi.org/10.1007/s00213-006-0457-5) 


Grob, C. S., Danforth, A. L., Chopra, G. S., Hagerty, M., McKay, C. R., Halberstadt, A. L., & Greer, G. R. (2011). Pilot Study of Psilocybin Treatment for Anxiety in Patients With Advanced-Stage Cancer. _Archives of General Psychiatry_, _68_(1), 71–78. [https://doi.org/10.1001/archgenpsychiatry.2010.116](https://doi.org/10.1001/archgenpsychiatry.2010.116) 


Hoffman, D. D., Singh, M., & Prakash, C. (2015). The Interface Theory of Perception. _Psychonomic Bulletin & Review_, _22_(6), 1480–1506. [https://doi.org/10.3758/s13423-015-0890-8](https://doi.org/10.3758/s13423-015-0890-8) 


_Hopalong Attractor—Maple Help_. (n.d.). Retrieved March 29, 2022, from [https://www.maplesoft.com/support/help/maple/view.aspx?path=MathApps/HopalongAttractor](https://www.maplesoft.com/support/help/maple/view.aspx?path=MathApps/HopalongAttractor) 


Kahn, Adam S, and Aaron Castelán Cargile. “Immersive and Interactive Awe: Evoking Awe via Presence in Virtual Reality and Online Videos to Prompt Prosocial Behavior.” _Human Communication Research_ 47, no. 4 (October 1, 2021): 387–417.[ https://doi.org/10.1093/hcr/hqab007](https://doi.org/10.1093/hcr/hqab007).


Keltner, D., & Haidt, J. (2003). Approaching awe, a moral, spiritual, and aesthetic emotion. _Cognition and Emotion_, _17_(2), 297–314. [https://doi.org/10.1080/02699930302297](https://doi.org/10.1080/02699930302297) 


Krok, D. (2015). The Role of Meaning in Life Within the Relations of Religious Coping and Psychological Well-Being. _Journal of Religion and Health_, _54_(6), 2292–2308. [https://doi.org/10.1007/s10943-014-9983-3](https://doi.org/10.1007/s10943-014-9983-3) 


Lavallee, C. F., Koren, S. A., & Persinger, M. A. (2011). A Quantitative Electroencephalographic Study of Meditation and Binaural Beat Entrainment. _The Journal of Alternative and Complementary Medicine_, _17_(4), 351–355. [https://doi.org/10.1089/acm.2009.0691](https://doi.org/10.1089/acm.2009.0691) 


Levin, M. (2021). Bioelectrical approaches to cancer as a problem of the scaling of the cellular self. _Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology_, _165_, 102–113. [https://doi.org/10.1016/j.pbiomolbio.2021.04.007](https://doi.org/10.1016/j.pbiomolbio.2021.04.007) 


Lewis-Williams, J. D., Dowson, T. A., Bahn, P. G., Bandi, H.-G., Bednarik, R. G., Clegg, J., Consens, M., Davis, W., Delluc, B., Delluc, G., Faulstich, P., Halverson, J., Layton, R., Martindale, C., Mirimanov, V., Turner, C. G., Vastokas, J. M., Winkelman, M., & Wylie, A. (1988). The Signs of All Times: Entoptic Phenomena in Upper Palaeolithic Art [and Comments and Reply]. _Current Anthropology_, _29_(2), 201–245.


Liu, P., Stepanova, E., Kitson, A., Schiphorst, T., & Riecke, B. (2022). _Virtual Transcendent Dream: Empowering People through Embodied Flying in Virtual Reality_. 1–18. [https://doi.org/10.1145/3491102.3517677](https://doi.org/10.1145/3491102.3517677) 


López, M. A. (2020). _Brainwave Entrainment to Improve Problem-solving skills in People with the Neurodevelopmental Disorder ADHD_. 8.


Mangan, B. (2007). Cognition, Fringe Consciousness, and the Legacy of William James. In M. Velmans & S. Schneider (Eds.), _The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness_ (pp. 671–685). Blackwell.


Mangan, B. B. (1991). _Meaning and the Structure of Consciousness: An Essay in Psycho-Aesthetics_ [PhD Thesis]. University of California, Berkeley.


Maslow, A. H. (1964). _Religions, Values, and Peak Experiences_. Ohio State University Press. [https://www.academia.edu/37619593/Religions_Values_and_Peak_Experiences_Abraham_H_Maslow](https://www.academia.edu/37619593/Religions_Values_and_Peak_Experiences_Abraham_H_Maslow) 


_MLQ.pdf_. (n.d.). Retrieved May 26, 2022, from [http://www.michaelfsteger.com/wp-content/uploads/2012/08/MLQ.pdf](http://www.michaelfsteger.com/wp-content/uploads/2012/08/MLQ.pdf) 


Okrent, M. (1993). Review of Being-in-the-World: A Commentary on Heidegger’s Being and Time, Division I. [Review of _Review of Being-in-the-World: A Commentary on Heidegger’s Being and Time, Division I._, by H. L. Dreyfus]. _The Philosophical Review_, _102_(2), 290–293. [https://doi.org/10.2307/2186049](https://doi.org/10.2307/2186049) 


Ratcliffe, M. (2005). The Feeling of Being. _J. Conscious. Stud._, _12_.


Russell, J. A., & Barrett, L. F. (1999). Core affect, prototypical emotional episodes, and other things called emotion: Dissecting the elephant. _Journal of Personality and Social Psychology_, _76_(5), 805–819. [https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.76.5.805](https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.76.5.805) 


Safdari Sharabiani, A. (2021). Genuine empathy with inanimate objects. _Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences_, _20_(5), 831–846. [https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-020-09715-w](https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-020-09715-w) 


Sechehaye, M. A. (1951). _Symbolic realization; a new method of psychotherapy applied to a case of schizophrenia_ (p. 184). International Universities Press.


Steger, M. F., Frazier, P., Oishi, S., & Kaler, M. (2006). The meaning in life questionnaire: Assessing the presence of and search for meaning in life. _Journal of Counseling Psychology_, _53_(1), 80–93. [https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-0167.53.1.80](https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-0167.53.1.80) 


Stendardi, D., Biscotto, F., Bertossi, E., & Ciaramelli, E. (2021). Present and future self in memory: The role of vmPFC in the self-reference effect. _Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience_, _16_(12), 1205–1213. [https://doi.org/10.1093/scan/nsab07](https://doi.org/10.1093/scan/nsab07) 1


_Subjective effect index—PsychonautWiki_. (2022, April 17). [https://web.archive.org/web/20220417154904/https://psychonautwiki.org/wiki/Subjective_effects_index](https://web.archive.org/web/20220417154904/https://psychonautwiki.org/wiki/Subjective_effects_index) 


_SUBPAC - The New Way to Experience Sound: Feel it.<sup>TM</sup>_. (n.d.). SUBPAC. Retrieved May 11, 2021, from [https://subpac.com/](https://subpac.com/) 


Tegmark, M. (2008). The Mathematical Universe. _Foundations of Physics_, _38_(2), 101–150. [https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-007-9186-9](https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-007-9186-9) 


Thompson, J. (2022). Awe Narratives: A Mindfulness Practice to Enhance Resilience and Wellbeing. _Frontiers in Psychology_, _13_, 840944. [https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2022.840944](https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2022.840944) 


Torgler, B. (2007). Determinants of superstition. _The Journal of Socio-Economics_, _36_(5), 713–733. [https://doi.org/10.1016/j.socec.2007.01.007](https://doi.org/10.1016/j.socec.2007.01.007) 


Vermetten, E., Krediet, E., Bostoen, T., Breeksema, J. J., Schoevers, R. A., & van den Brink, W. (2020). [Psychedelics in the treatment of PTSD]. _Tijdschrift Voor Psychiatrie_, _62_(8), 640–649.


Villar, S., Carrera, P., & Oceja, L. (2022). From aesthetics to ethics: Testing the link between an emotional experience of awe and the motive of quixoteism on (un)ethical behavior. _Motivation and Emotion_, 1–13. [https://doi.org/10.1007/s11031-022-09935-4](https://doi.org/10.1007/s11031-022-09935-4) 


Ward, S. J., & King, L. A. (2016). Poor but Happy? Income, Happiness, and Experienced and Expected Meaning in Life. _Social Psychological and Personality Science_, _7_(5), 463–470. [https://doi.org/10.1177/1948550615627865](https://doi.org/10.1177/1948550615627865) 


Winkelman, M. J. (2017). The Mechanisms of Psychedelic Visionary Experiences: Hypotheses from Evolutionary Psychology. _Frontiers in Neuroscience_, _11_, 539. [https://doi.org/10.3389/fnins.2017.00539](https://doi.org/10.3389/fnins.2017.00539) 

Appendix

Meaning in Life Questionnaire

This is taken directly from Michael F. Steger’s (creator of questionnaire) website (MLQ.Pdf, n.d.).


Please take a moment to think about what makes your life feel important to you.

Please respond to the following statements as truthfully and accurately as you can, and

also please remember that these are very subjective questions and that there are no right

or wrong answers. Please answer according to the scale below:

Absolutely Untrue \ 1 Mostly Untrue

2

Somewhat Untrue

3

Can’t Say True or False

4

Somewhat True

5

Mostly

True

6

Absolutely True

7

1. I understand my life’s meaning.

2. I am looking for something that makes my life feel meaningful.

3. I am always looking to find my life’s purpose.

4. My life has a clear sense of purpose.

5. I have a good sense of what makes my life meaningful.

6. I have discovered a satisfying life purpose.

7. I am always searching for something that makes my life feel significant.

8. I am seeking a purpose or mission for my life.

9. My life has no clear purpose.

10. I am searching for meaning in my life.

MLQ scoring:

Presence = 1, 4, 5, 6, & 9-reverse-coded

Search = 2, 3, 7, 8, & 10

Notes


  1. The direct perception of reality is often called naïve realism, a view that—in its purest form—claims that “…things appear a certain way to you because you are directly presented with aspects of the world, and—in the case we are focusing on—things appear white to you, because you are directly presented with some white snow” (Crane & French, 2021). ↩︎

  2. This is a broad shift across disciplines. In biology, this has led to new ways to examine things like bioelectricity (Levin, 2021). In physics, this has steadily revealed itself through quantum and astrophysics, where substances can be replaced with their properties as they become very small or very large (Tegmark, 2008). ↩︎

  3. Affect has been wielded so many way that it may have lost its intended meaning, but the affect we describe here is bodily feeling, i.e., the way things feel to us—this is understood to be prior to full-bodied emotions, which are constructed from affect and the other factors we discuss. ↩︎

  4. Soma is a fictional wonder drug from a science fiction dystopia that blocks out all the “negative” emotions, such as pain, grief, and anger. ↩︎

  5. There are at least two other senses of “meaning” that are commonly used: meaning in language and meaning in metaphysics. Meaning in language is quite similar to immediate meaning. Just as language cannot be reduced to symbols or shapes, so too can immediate meaning not be reduced to neurons firing or utterances of meaning. In metaphysics, meaning takes on the role of reference–this is mostly distinct from the other senses of meaning except for its directness. ↩︎

  6. For example, I went to the UPS store today to drop off some tennis racquets I demoed. I demoed these because I am looking for a new racquet that will be better on my arm. I care about this because I like being healthy. Being healthy helps me in lots of ways, especially thinking. The things I want to do in my life involve me thinking good. Therefore, going to the UPS store could be said to align to the meaning in life I’m pursuing. ↩︎

  7. Fallenness is not–in traditional Heidegger fashion–presented as a moral judgment. Idleness, ambiguity, and curiosity (taken to be a hedonistic pursuit of pleasure) do of course carry negative connotations, but Heidegger tries to present (as per usual) treats this as an impartial observation. We tend to behave in a fallen way and that’s all there is to it. ↩︎

  8. Effective Altruism is a movement/belief that there are more or less quantitatively useful ways of going about doing good. ↩︎

  9. The _Red Cross _is a well-intentioned but inefficient non-profit that supports and provides a wide variety of humanitarian projects ↩︎

  10. This being the constructed world of our experience, not some objective world—everything we experience is through our mental models. For more, see Hoffman’s Interface Theory of Perception (Hoffman et al., 2015). ↩︎

  11. To me, reducing Meaningfulness to a signal takes us exactly one step too far towards substance ontology. We can describe Meaningfulness as a signal and treat it as such in our models and predictions, but Meaningfulness is exactly what it is in light of how it works in reality. To reduce it to a generic abstraction like a signal is to describe something that is not Meaningfulness but that walks and talks like it sometimes. ↩︎

  12. Among these are awe, which–though interesting–limits our inquiry to a kind of hedonic sideshow. Awe doesn’t motivate our lives on any deeper level. See also: emotion, pleasure, pain, happiness, suffering. These are all interesting and apparently tractable lines of inquiry but they all miss the point–none of these matter unless meaning undergirds them. ↩︎

  13. Barring Neurolink branching out into canine devices, with great success ↩︎

  14. Practitioners of meditation and psychedelic users have reported a loss of a sense of self/self-identity (which does show up in some neural correlates work (Stendardi et al., 2021)), but even these experiences have a center–it’s just that the immediate center is experienced as being distinct from the narrative center. ↩︎

  15. Empathy loosely fits this–we project what we feel onto what we reflexively think that other things might feel. ↩︎

  16. This environmental part of the model can and should be further subdivided, but, for the sake of simplicity, we will group these complex aspects into a single catchall–environment. ↩︎

  17. The loose justification for such an experiment is the assumption that religious people are more likely to attribute intentionality to phenomena that are difficult to rationalize (Torgler, 2007) and that this would manifest itself in how they interact with their environment. ↩︎

  18. Non-human animals could of course have a simpler, prototypical version of this. They lack language, but do have rudimentary forms of communication and social dynamics. But without the abstraction and creativity we enjoy, narrative meaning should be expected to be extremely limited. ↩︎

  19. There have been many candidate questionnaires put forth but–for better or for worse–the one used by most psychology studies today is the Meaning in Life Questionnaire (Steger et al., 2006) (more on this in the main text and in the appendix). ↩︎

  20. Immediate meaning is not treated as a standalone subject of inquiry. Instead, the closest we get are similar kinds of concepts: affordance, theory of mind, and religious devotion. Peak experiences would work (as they are immediately meaningful) but we do not administer tests of peak experience. ↩︎

  21. This seeming contradiction is found in meditative practice, where practitioners are told to focus on the breath and then allow all their other sensory data to flow in, until the experience becomes unified. ↩︎

  22. There are at least two senses in which self is used–individualistically and collectivistically. The individualistic self is our perception of our self as having a permanent set of personality traits and beliefs. The collectivist self involves our perception of ourselves as members of a group (Chiao et al., 2009). ↩︎

  23. Even lyrics are not meaningful in that they are just sound waves until we process and transform them into something that we perceive to be meaningful ↩︎

  24. Though we don’t foresee this being an issue in the pilot study, the Visualizer involves rotation and bright, moving colors, which could affect those sensitive to these stimuli. ↩︎

  25. The ideal amount of time will likely vary per person–as we’re targeting meditative, hypnagogic states, every person will have their own onboarding curve as they become entrained and attending. The 8 minute limit here was chosen for purely pragmatic reasons (cost per participant). ↩︎

  26. This and other changes were made through feedback from collaborators, all with the intention of reducing the likelihood that participants would reach peak experiences in the control, without changing the information we present them over time. ↩︎

  27. Relative to baseline and control ↩︎

  28. Online studies mean that participants can potentially be distracted in many different ways and have different computer specs (such as frame rate and refresh rate). ↩︎

  29. This claim is not supported by a peer-reviewed paper, but it is readily reproducible in the wild. ↩︎

  30. With eye-tracking, fixations could signify attention/flow and saccades a loss of flow/inattention. ↩︎